The argument on the question of ends and means began not in the 1970’s over Bigfoot but back in
the 1950’s over the Yeti. Loren Coleman, in a book devoted to Tom Slick, a Texas millionaire
who mounted two Himalayan expeditions searching for the yeti, has this to say on the issue:
On March 18 and 19 (1957), the Nepalese government forbade all foreign mountaineers from killing,
injuring, or capturing a yeti. ... Tom Slick's expeditions, of course, helped open up the whole debate on
the ethics of killing zoological specimens. During the pre-Slick years, the giant panda, for example, was
routinely killed and mounted for museums around the world before anyone stopped to consider what
effect this action would have on the breeding population. Pandas were killed first to provide evidence
that they even existed, then as prized natural history exhibits, and finally captured alive as animals of
choice for zoological gardens. Today the giant panda is a symbol of endangered species, and no one
would even consider killing one for a museum or any other scientific purpose.
Slick entered the field of cryptozoology when the rules were just beginning to be redefined. His goal,
as he saw it, was to collect a specimen, alive or dead, to prove to the scientific world that the yeti existed.
By the late 1950s, the era of hunting and collecting was beginning to end. Slick's thoughts on killing
began to change, to reflect the times, and to mirror his own notions on the creatures' right to survive. ...
Slick received a good deal of bad press about his very "Texan" approach to the yeti hunt, especially from
British writers in England and India. (Tom Slick and the Search for the Yeti, 1989, pp. 59, 60)
If Tom Slick's thoughts on killing began to change back in the 1950’s, then the thoughts of John Green and Grover Krantz
haven't changed a wee bit over the past decades and present a magnificent relic of the pre-Slick era. Before dealing with this relic in detail, I would like to bring to the reader's attention certain views from the opposite camp. First, the final passage in an article by zoologist Edward W. Cronin, Jr., who returned from a two-year scientific expedition into Nepal convinced that the yeti exists:
Even though I am intrigued with the yeti, both for its scientific importance and for what it says about our
own interests and biases, I would be deeply saddened to have it discovered. ... If the yeti is an old form
that we have driven into the mountains, now we would be driving it into the zoos. We would gain another
possession, another ragged exhibit in the concrete world of the zoological park, another Latin name to
enter on our scientific ledgers. But what about the wild creature that now roams free of man in the forests
of the Himalayas? Every time man asserts his mastery over nature, he gains something in knowledge,
but loses something in spirit. ("The Yeti", The Atlantic, November 1973, p. 53)
This passage is remarkable not so much for its message as for coming from a scientist. If anthropologist Krantz seeks to
discover a hominoid by any means, then zoologist Cronin "would be deeply saddened" by the discovery
even with the best of means. Cronin is not the only scientist to think so. Apparently, the latter extreme
is an inevitable reaction to the former extreme. An ever growing number of laymen and academics are
getting weary of man's treatment of animals. One manifestation of these feelings and views is the
emergence of the animal-rights movement, which boasts of a solid theoretical foundation provided
by philosopher Peter Singer's 1975 book, Animal Liberation: A New Ethics for Our Treatment of Animals.
The book’s message is very relevant to the theme under discussions here and prompts me to give some
crucial quotes from this subversive work:
The core of this book is the claim that to discriminate against beings solely on account of their species is
a form of prejudice, immoral and indefensible in the same way that discrimination on the basis of race is
immoral and indefensible. (p. 270)
Speciesism the word is not an attractive one, but I can think of no better term is a prejudice or
attitude of bias toward the interests of members of one's own species and against those of members of
other species. (p. 3)
The distinction between humans and other animals is not a sharp division but rather a continuum along
which we move gradually and with overlaps between the species, from simple capacities for enjoyment
and satisfaction to more complex ones. (p. 266)
Once we ask why it should be that all humans including infants, mental defectives, criminal
psychopaths Hitler, Stalin, and the rest have some kind of dignity or worth that no elephant, pig or
chimpanzee can ever achieve, we see that this question is as difficult to answer as our original request
for some relevant fact that justifies the inequality of humans and other animals. (pp. 267,268)
If possessing a higher degree of intelligence does not entitle one human to use another for his own ends,
how can it entitle humans to exploit nonhumans for the same purpose? (p. 7)
With the most intensive care possible, there are retarded infants who can never achieve the intelligence
level of a dog. (p. 20)
The author quotes English philosopher, Jeremy Bentham, (1748 -1832):
... a full-grown horse or dog is beyond comparison a more rational, as well as a more conversable
animal, than an infant of a day or a week or even a month old. The question is not, Can they reason? or
Can they talk? but Can they suffer? (p. 8)
The capacity for suffering and enjoyment is a prerequisite for having interests at all... A stone does not
have interests because it cannot suffer. (p. 9)
The basic principle of equality does not require equal or identical treatment; it requires equal
consideration. Equal consideration for different beings may lead to different treatment and different
rights. (p. 3). (Aside: This passage reminds me of another philosopher's dictum: "From each
according to his capacity, to each according to his needs." - D.B.)
I conclude, then, that a rejection of speciesism does not imply that all lives are of equal worth. (p. 23)
If we love rocks, trees, plants, larks, and oxen equally, we may lose sight of the essential difference
between them, most importantly, the difference in degree of sentience. (p. 215)
Animal Liberation will require greater altruism on the part of human beings than any other liberation
movement. One reason for it is that, "The animals themselves are incapable of demanding their own
liberation." (pp. 272, 273).
"Animal Liberation is Human Liberation too." (p. XIV)
The book's jacket carries these words by Brigid Brophy: "As human animals, we must
stop hunting, hurting, enslaving, and eating our fellows. We are not the only species with
a right to life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness. Peter Singer puts the case comprehensively
and convincingly. Don't read him if you want to go on being a tyrant and a hypocrite."
Peter Singer's book was not yet published when I challenged John Green over the rights of Bigfoot, and
the book had not yet come my way when I argued the matter with Grover Krantz. In fact, it was only a
short time ago that I heard of and read about Animal Liberation. It was then that I realized my efforts
to uphold a fair deal for hominoids is just one aspect and an illustration of a wider movement inspired
by a book of philosophy. According to Singer:
Philosophy ought to question the basic assumptions of the age. Thinking through, critically and carefully,
what most of us take for granted is, I believe, the chief task of philosophy, and the task that makes
philosophy a worthwhile activity. (p. 263)
Singer questions the basic assumption of the age and what most of us take for granted. He is, therefore, a true philosopher.
Thank goodness mankind is still capable of giving birth to this kind of animal.
|